basic constructions:
strong axioms
further
Predicative mathematics is a way of doing mathematics without allowing impredicative definitions.
Informally, a definition is impredicative if it refers to a totality which includes the thing being defined. For example, the definition of a particular real number as the least upper bound of a given set is impredicative, because it characterizes as a particular element of some set (the upper bounds of ) which includes . Possibly can be defined in some other way and then proved to be the least upper bound of , but to define it thus by fiat is impredicative.
There are (at least) two broad schools of the foundations of predicative mathematics that don't talk much to each other: one school that uses lower-order forms of higher-order logic (or the set theory that this justifies) and classical logic, and a constructive school that uses first-order type theory (or the set theory that this justifies) and intuitionistic logic. The common ground is that both schools reject power sets; other axioms may vary. Here we tend to think of what predicative mathematics allows the category of sets to be.
Constructive predicativists sometimes accept principles (such as function sets and the axiom of replacement) that classical predicativists must reject because they imply impredicative results using excluded middle. Such mathematics may be called weakly predicative.
Not all of these axioms are rejected by all predicativists, but they at least come under some suspicion.
The axiom of infinity is not usually considered impredicative, but we list it anyway, as it is needed for the others to have force. Mathematics that does not require this axiom, finite mathematics, can be interpreted in a predicative framework even if it uses many of the axioms below.
The axiom that any set has a power set is perhaps the fundamental feature missing from predicative mathematics. In particular, the sequence
may be accepted in part, but not forever.
The failure of the power set axiom means that the category of sets is not an elementary topos.
The constructive school generally accepts the axiom of replacement but not unbounded forms of the axiom of separation. (This choice is not available to the classical school, since replacement and excluded middle together imply full separation.)
Naïvely, the axiom of separation says that, if is a set and is a function from to the set of truth values, then there is a set
To be precise, however, this should be written as a predicate in the language of set theory. The form of separation justified by type theory and such structural set theories as ETCS requires the quantifiers in this predicate to be guarded by sets; unbounded separation is the generalisation of this to arbitrary quantifiers.
Arguably, the impredicative core of both separation and power sets (in the presence of bounded separation) is limited separation: separation in which the quantifiers in may be guarded by power classes.
We need more on this, particularly with regards to the classical school and replacement.
One sometimes speaks of forbidding function sets instead of power sets. That is, it is the sequence
that is avoided.
Of course, function sets can be constructed out of power sets (using bounded separation), so forbidding function sets certainly forbids power sets. The converse holds if there is a set of truth values.
With excluded middle, the set of truth values is easy to achieve, as ; in particular, if you have , then you certainly have . So the classical school of predicativism rejects function sets.
The constructive school, however, often accepts function sets (thus being weakly predicative). In this school, the sequence above is fine. Actually, the slightly stronger axiom of subset collection is adopted by Peter Aczel's and justified by Per Martin-Löf's .
Brouwer, on the other hand, did not accept the sequence above, although his followers differ on when (if ever) it stops.
Classical predicativists of course accept excluded middle; otherwise they would be constructivists. But from the perspective of weakly predicative constructive mathematics, excluded middle is impredicative, since it implies power sets (given function sets) and unbounded separation (given replacement).
Most foundations of mathematics are predicative in one sense: no set may belong to itself. This (or rather, a certain strengthening of this) is the axiom of foundation. An alternative is the axiom of antifoundation, which explicitly allows for and tames such sets as , where . Indeed, this equation is a perfectly good way to define using antifoundation, yet this is about as impredicative as a definition can get.
Once one accepts the axiom of infinity, there's not much objection to accepting more general inductive types such as inductive-inductive types and quotient inductive types; these are sets that are defined recursively much like a natural numbers object. Categorially, we may see these as initial algebras of certain functors on . Coinductive types, which are the final coalgebras of these functors, also exist in impredicative theories, but not predicatively.
A different sort of impredicativity is to be found in some type theories, in which, roughly speaking, one is allowed to define “functions” whose “domain” is the class of all types. For instance, one might be able to form a type called , which has the property that an inhabitant of that type is a “function” which assigns to every type , an endomorphism of . This is clearly impredicative, since the type is also a possible value of .
The philosophy behind this sort of impredicative definition is that any inhabitant of such a type must be defined “uniformly” enough that it uses no details about the type , and thus can equally well be applied to any . For instance, consider the operation which assigns to every the identity ; this is defined in exactly the same way for every , and hence inhabits the type .
This sort of impredicativism can be shown to be incompatible with impredicative set-theoretic axioms such as power sets; see this paper of Andy Pitts. Since such type theories generally do have function types, it follows that they cannot be classical.
So what is the category of sets in predicative mathematics?
At bottom, let us suppose that is a Heyting pretopos; this is a category whose internal logic is first-order and contains only constructions that don't require any of the above axioms.
Since we're not doing finite mathematics, we may also include a natural numbers object. In fact, we could include more general inductive types, since these are no harder to justify philosophically than , although the proofs that these exist if does rely on possibly impredicative axioms. Then is a Heyting -pretopos.
If you accept function sets, then is locally cartesian closed and thus a -pretopos. In this case, is enough to get all -types, so we have a --pretopos. If you accept excluded middle, then is a Boolean pretopos or even a Boolean -pretopos. But a Boolean -pretopos is necessarily a topos, which would make the theory impredicative.
However, is still a Grothendieck topos, defined as a category of sheaves or in terms of Giraud's characterisation. We require the existence of power sets to prove the theorem that such a category is an elementary topos, so predicatively a Grothendieck topos may not be an elementary topos at all.
An important question in predicative mathematics is the status of the set of real numbers. This set is often constructed as a subset of or as a subquotient of , neither of which can be formed in an arbitrary Heyting -pretopos. The latter can be formed in a --pretopos, but it is not necessarily correct.
The constructive school of predicativism can construct in various ways. One method is to use directly, but this will only go so far unless something is done to prove that it is Dedekind-complete. This will follow from weak countable choice (), which is accepted by most constructive schools. Using subset collection, a variation on is possible which can be proved Dedekind-complete without .
However, not all constructive predicative mathematics accept subset collection or weak countable choice. Another method is to use a predicative version of , where given a -frame , -Dedekind cuts are defined as pairs of functions from the rational numbers to , which represent the open subsets of , rather than pairs of functions into the class of propositions. is defined as the set of all -Dedekind cuts, or as the -Dedekind complete archimedean field. This will ensure that the set of real numbers is a set rather than a proper class, at the cost of Dedekind completeness, which always results in a proper class in constructive predicative mathematics. Nevertheless, a significant portion of real analysis? could be developed using this approach, such as differential calculus, integral calculus, and differential geometry.
It is also possible to assert the existence of by fiat, much like exists by the axiom of infinity. This is the approach taken by the classical school; they use instead of directly, but these are isomorphic by excluded middle. This is natural from the perspective of predicative set theory as a weak form of higher-order logic; you assert the existence of , , and maybe , then stop.
There is also the question of what exactly it means to say that exists; is it a set or a proper class? Without function sets, the distinction between these is not clear-cut; higher-order logic suggests a hierarchy of more and more proper (less and less small) classes rather than a single unified notion of set and class, which is similar to the concept of a universe in a topos for impredicative set theory. If you allow only as a proper class, then you are basically still doing finite mathematics; if you allow only as a proper class, then you are doing predicative mathematics.
How much of mathematics can be done predicatively?
A surprisingly large amount of mathematics can be formalised, using various coding tricks, in a theory in which is a set but is a proper class. This is somewhat easier in Nik Weaver?'s ‘conceptualist’ approach, which accepts as a proper class (so that and are small); the encoding is not really more complicated than what is usually done in material set theory for ordered pairs and the like. Note that these are conservative over Peano arithmetic (); that is, anything expressible in and provable in these systems is provable in (which certainly cannot be said of ZFC or ETCS, which prove the consistency of ).
Constructive mathematics generally requires great care with anything after the middle of the 19th century other than basic discrete mathematics, but requiring it to be predicative does not usually add much difficulty, as long as function sets are allowed. This even extends to category theory, which is not usually contemplated in the classical approach. (However, the internal logic of a --pretopos is certainly not conservative over ; it already proves consistency of the latter.)
Solomon Feferman; Relationships between Constructive, Predicative and Classical Systems of Analysis (PDF).
Nik Weaver; papers on conceptualism.
from the Standford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
Discussion of predicative toposes is in
Ieke Moerdijk, Erik Palmgren, Type theories, toposes and constructive set theory: predicative aspects of algebraic set theory Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 114(1-3):155–201, 2002
Benno van den Berg, Predicative toposes (arXiv:1207.0959)
Constructive predicative definitions of the real numbers are discussed in
Univalent Foundations Project, Homotopy Type Theory – Univalent Foundations of Mathematics (2013)
Mike: Is there a formal definition of “impredicative” other than “whatever predicativists don’t like?” In particular, I don’t understand why exponentials are any less problematic than power sets. If I have the set , can’t I then use it to define a new function in terms of this set that contains the function being defined?
Toby: Arguably, Brouwer's school doesn't accept exponentiation, although they accept some cases of it (such as ). I've never heard them call it ‘impredicative’, however. Someday I want to figure out how much can be done using both W-types and co-W-types (equivalently, final coalgebras of polynomial functors) but not exponentiation. (So far, I can construct as the final coalgebra of , but I can't prove that it is !)
This discussion began at Grothendieck topology:
Mike: The passage from a collection of covering families (“coverage”) to a collection of sieves (“Grothendieck coverage”) is a higher-order construction. One thing this means is that you can’t do it if you happen to be a predicativist; thus to study “predicative sheaves” you need to use covering families instead of sieves. Another thing it means, which I care more about, is that many common coverages can be discussed in the first-order language of a category, while the corresponding Grothendieck coverages require an external set theory. For instance, I can say “a pretopos is a stack for its coherent coverage” in the first-order language of a category, but not if I replace “coverage” by “Grothendieck coverage.”
Toby: If you're going to be a predicativist, then you really have to take the attitude that a structure is defined by an arbitrary family of sets, and the closure conditions can be used afterwards (if the concept is really susceptible to predicativist understanding) to define equivalence of structures. (Note that a ‘family of subsets’ of is equivalent to an index set and a single subset of .)
For example, define a topological space to be a set equipped with an arbitrary family of subsets, called ‘subbasic open sets’. Define an ‘open set’ to be a subset whose every point belongs to the intersection of some finite family of subbasic open sets. Define two topologies on a given set to be equivalent if every subbasic open set in either is open in the other. All of this is predicative.
Actually, if you want to be finitist (in the sense that you have no axiom of infinity and hence no language to state that a family is ‘finite’) as well, then you must be subtler. Define a topological space to be a set equipped with a family of subsets (now called ‘basic open sets’) such that nullary and binary intersections of basic open sets are basic open sets (or at least always contain one). Define an ‘open set’ to be a subset whose every point belongs to some basic open set. Define equivalence as before.
These justify the importance of the concepts of ‘basis’ and ‘subbasis’ for a topology, taught in schools today. Perhaps there is a similar justification for ‘coverage’? (Or for ‘Grothendieck pretopology’, for that matter?)
Mike: Okay, well, I retract my comment about predicativism, since it is clear that I don’t understand (nor, really, care much about) predicative math. But my other comment about being first-order still stands.
Toby: I'd hoped that my example might give predicatvism (at least in the sense of not having a small set of truth value) some interest. I expect that it's related to being first-order and internalisable; after all, the internal logic of many categories is predicative, and rejecting power sets may be seen as an attempt to do all of mathematics in a first-order way. Ah, well.
Mike: Perhaps we should move the discussion about predicativity to predicativism? (Feel free to do so, snipping out the relevant paragraphs of my responses, if you like.) I also once had the thought that predicative math was interesting because of the internal logic of non-toposes. However, I have not encountered any naturally occurring examples (relative to classical mathematics) of, say, locally cartesian closed pretoposes which are not actually toposes. I am not a philosophical constructivist. I like constructive proofs for the same reason I like to prove things about arbitrary rings rather than about the integers: the result is more general and applies in more contexts. Toposes (of sheaves, usually) arise naturally in classical mathematics, so it is a good thing to know what proofs can be interpreted internally in a topos. If I knew a similar class of locally cartesian closed pretoposes that arose naturally in classical mathematics, I would be more favorably inclined towards predicativism.
Toby: Philosophically, I'm a pluralist, so I also like constructivism (in the sense of Bishop, without classically false axioms) for its wider applicability. And I even like mathematics with classically false axioms as much (potentially) as classical mathematics and wish it were more fully developed. But while you might be interested in such mathematics only if the categories that it can be internalised in come up in actual mathematical practice, it's enough for me if it comes up in actual philosophical practice; that is, if there is a school of constructivists interested in working with certain restrictions and axioms, then I'm interested in knowing what mathematics might apply there, and I try to do mathematics so that it will apply there.
(To be honest, I almost convinced myself that I'm interested, for their own sake as the ‘right’ way to do things, in foundations that amount to working in a locally cartesian closed pretopos whose category of lex endofunctors has enough injectives, but as soon as I got as far as figuring that out, I got onto something else.)
I hope that predicativism can still tell us something about how “a pretopos is a stack for its coherent coverage” works where “a pretopos is a stack for its coherent Grothendieck coverage” doesn't. But it's already enough to interest me in predicativism that there are predicativists.
Mike: Fair enough. I can understand that, even if it’s not my philosophy.
Actually, on further reflection, it’s not really accurate to say that I don’t care about predicativism. It’s the specific variety of predicativism that accepts things like exponentials, W-types, fullness, and/or collection, but not power sets, that I have trouble justifying. Because I do care about what can be made first-order, I care about the internal logic of a Heyting category, which could be called “even more” predicative; I’m just not used to giving it that label. And the category of classes in a membership-based set theory is a good example of a positive Heyting category that doesn’t even have exponentials.
Toby: I care about that too, and since predicativism in practice is a vague term that might not allow exponentials either (as Brouwer didn't), the practice might still be wroth examining for that purpose. But that is not something that can be established theoretically, so I'll just use any useful examples that I see, and leave it at that.
Mike: I realized that there is a class of locally cartesian closed extensive Heyting categories that I care about: extensive quasitoposes. I used to believe that the correct internal logic of a quasitopos used the fibration of regular subobjects, rather than the fibration of all subobjects, but that logic is kind of poorly behaved, for instance it doesn’t satisfy function comprehension (if you prove that for all there exists a unique such that blah, then all you get is a span where is monic and epic). Quasitoposes are always locally cartesian closed Heyting categories, and I think it’s fair to say that all the interesting ones are extensive as well.
Any quasitopos that is a pretopos is in fact a topos, so I still don’t know any interesting locally cartesian closed pretoposes that aren’t toposes. One could take the ex/reg completion of an extensive quasitopos to get an interesting pretopos, but I don’t know whether it would still be locally cartesian closed. But any locally cartesian closed Heyting category has an internal logic which is predicative with exponentials. I wonder which quasitoposes have W-types and stuff like that.
Mike: Also, the ex/lex completion takes extensive categories to pretoposes and preserves local cartesian closedness. So, in particular, the ex/lex completion of a topos is locally cartesian closed pretopos which is not, in general, a topos. I’m not sure what interesting categories of this sort there are.
Todd: Interesting discussion. Just wanted to add that I’d recently been thinking about small-colimit completions of toposes, which are examples of ex/lex completions of toposes that are (seemingly) almost never toposes.
Last revised on May 7, 2022 at 09:56:17. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.