nLab logical framework

Contents

Context

Deduction and Induction

Type theory

natural deduction metalanguage, practical foundations

  1. type formation rule
  2. term introduction rule
  3. term elimination rule
  4. computation rule

type theory (dependent, intensional, observational type theory, homotopy type theory)

syntax object language

computational trinitarianism =
propositions as types +programs as proofs +relation type theory/category theory

logicset theory (internal logic of)category theorytype theory
propositionsetobjecttype
predicatefamily of setsdisplay morphismdependent type
proofelementgeneralized elementterm/program
cut rulecomposition of classifying morphisms / pullback of display mapssubstitution
introduction rule for implicationcounit for hom-tensor adjunctionlambda
elimination rule for implicationunit for hom-tensor adjunctionapplication
cut elimination for implicationone of the zigzag identities for hom-tensor adjunctionbeta reduction
identity elimination for implicationthe other zigzag identity for hom-tensor adjunctioneta conversion
truesingletonterminal object/(-2)-truncated objecth-level 0-type/unit type
falseempty setinitial objectempty type
proposition, truth valuesubsingletonsubterminal object/(-1)-truncated objecth-proposition, mere proposition
logical conjunctioncartesian productproductproduct type
disjunctiondisjoint union (support of)coproduct ((-1)-truncation of)sum type (bracket type of)
implicationfunction set (into subsingleton)internal hom (into subterminal object)function type (into h-proposition)
negationfunction set into empty setinternal hom into initial objectfunction type into empty type
universal quantificationindexed cartesian product (of family of subsingletons)dependent product (of family of subterminal objects)dependent product type (of family of h-propositions)
existential quantificationindexed disjoint union (support of)dependent sum ((-1)-truncation of)dependent sum type (bracket type of)
logical equivalencebijection setobject of isomorphismsequivalence type
support setsupport object/(-1)-truncationpropositional truncation/bracket type
n-image of morphism into terminal object/n-truncationn-truncation modality
equalitydiagonal function/diagonal subset/diagonal relationpath space objectidentity type/path type
completely presented setsetdiscrete object/0-truncated objecth-level 2-type/set/h-set
setset with equivalence relationinternal 0-groupoidBishop set/setoid with its pseudo-equivalence relation an actual equivalence relation
equivalence class/quotient setquotientquotient type
inductioncolimitinductive type, W-type, M-type
higher inductionhigher colimithigher inductive type
-0-truncated higher colimitquotient inductive type
coinductionlimitcoinductive type
presettype without identity types
set of truth valuessubobject classifiertype of propositions
domain of discourseuniverseobject classifiertype universe
modalityclosure operator, (idempotent) monadmodal type theory, monad (in computer science)
linear logic(symmetric, closed) monoidal categorylinear type theory/quantum computation
proof netstring diagramquantum circuit
(absence of) contraction rule(absence of) diagonalno-cloning theorem
synthetic mathematicsdomain specific embedded programming language

homotopy levels

semantics

Foundations

foundations

The basis of it all

 Set theory

set theory

Foundational axioms

foundational axioms

Removing axioms

Contents

Idea

A logical framework is a formal metalanguage for deductive systems, such as logic, natural deduction, type theories, sequent calculus, etc. Of course, like any formal system, these systems can be described in any sufficiently strong metalanguage. However, all logical systems of this type share certain distinguishing features, so it is helpful to have a particular metalanguage which is well-adapted to describing systems with those features.

Much of the description below is taken from (Harper).

Overview

The sentences of a logical framework are called judgments. It turns out that in deductive systems, there are two kinds of non-basic forms that arise very commonly, which we may call

  • hypothetical judgments: one judgment is a logical consequence of some others.
  • generic judgments: a judgment that is made generally for all values of some parameters, each ranging over a “domain” or “syntactic category”. (Note that a “syntactic category” in this sense is unrelated to the notion of syntactic category that is a category built out of syntax; here we mean “category” in its informal sense of a subgrouping, so that for instance we have one syntactic category of “types” and another of “terms”.)

These two forms turn out to have many parallel features, e.g. reflexivity and transitivity of hypothetical judgments correspond to variable-use and substitution in generic judgments. Appealing to the propositions as types principle, therefore, it is convenient to describe a system in which they are actually both instances of the same thing. That is, we identify the notion of evidence for a judgment with the notion of object of a syntactic category.

This leads to a notion that we will call an LF-type. Thus we will have types such as

  • The LF-type of evidence for some judgment.
  • The LF-type of objects of a syntactic category.

We will also have some general type-forming operations. Perhaps surprisingly, it turns out that

are all that we need.

There is a potential confusion of terminology, because these LF-types in a logical framework (being itself a type theory) are distinct from the objects that may be called “types” in any particular logic we might be talking about inside the logical framework. Thus, for instance, when formalizing Martin-Lof type theory in a logical framework, there is an “LF-type” which is the type of objects of the syntactic category of MLTT-types. This is furthermore distinct from a type of types, which is itself an object of the syntactic category of MLTT-types, i.e. a term belonging to the LF-type of such.

The type theory of a logical framework often includes a second layer called LF-kinds, which enables us to classify families of LF-types. For instance, the universe TypeType of all LF-types is an LF-kind, as is the collection ATypeA\to\Type of all families of LF-types dependent on some LF-type AA. The LF-types and LF-kinds together are very similar to a pure type system with two sorts TypeType and KindKind, with axiom Type:KindType:Kind and rules (Type,Kind)(Type,Kind) and (Type,Type)(Type,Type), although there are some minor technical differences such as the treatment of definitional equality (PTS’s generally use untyped conversion, whereas logical frameworks are often formulated in a way so that only canonical forms exist).

Thus, we might have the following hierarchy of “universes”, which we summarize to fix the notation:

  • KindKind, the sort of LF-kinds
  • TypeType, the LF-kind of LF-types, i.e. Type:KindType:Kind.
  • tptp or typetype, the LF-type of all types in some object theory being discussed in LF, i.e. tp:Typetp : Type.
  • 𝒰 i\mathcal{U}_i, a type-of-types in such an object-theory, i.e. 𝒰 i:tp\mathcal{U}_i:tp.

Once we have set up the logical framework as a language, there are then two approaches to describing a given logic inside of it. See (Harper), and the other references, for more details.

Synthetic presentations

In a synthetic presentation, we use LF-types to represent the syntactic objects and judgments of the object theory. Thus, if the object theory is a type theory, then in LF we have things like:

  • an LF-type tptp of object-theory types
  • an LF-type tmtm of object-theory terms
  • a dependent LF-type of:tmtpTypeof : tm \to tp \to Type expressing the object-theory typing judgment. That is, for each object-theory term a:tma:tm and each object-theory type A:tpA:tp, we have an LF-type of(a,A)of(a,A) expressing the object-theory judgment “a:Aa:A” that aa is of type AA. According to propositions as types (at the level of the metatheory, sometimes called “judgments as types”), the elements of of(a,A)of(a,A) are “proofs” that a:Aa:A.

Note that we do not have to explicitly carry around an ambient context, as we sometimes do when presenting type theories in a more explicit style of a deductive system. This is because the notions of hypothetical and generic judgments are built into the logical framework and handled automatically by its contexts. We will discuss this further below.

Synthetic presentations are preferred by the school of Harper-Honsell-Plotkin and are generally used with implementations such as Twelf. They are very flexible and can be used to represent many different object-theories. Moreover, they generally support an adequacy theorem, that there is a compositional bijection between the syntactic objects of the object-theory, as usually presented, and the canonical forms of appropriate LF-type in its LF-presentation. Here “compositional” means that the bijection respects substitution.

Note that the adequacy theorem is a correspondence at the level of syntax; it does not even incorporate the object-theory notion of definitional equality! Two object-theory terms such as (λx.x)y(\lambda x.x)y and yy that are definitionally equal (by beta-reduction) are syntactically distinct, and hence also correspond to distinct syntactic entities in the LF-encoding. The definitional equality that relates them is represented by an element of the LF-type defeq()defeq(\dots) encoding the definitional-equality judgment of the object-theory. This is appropriate because such LF-encodings are used, among other things, for the study of the syntax of the object-theory, e.g. for proving properties of its definitional equality.

However, synthetic presentations do not make maximal use of the framework in the case when the object-theory is also a type theory whose judgments are “analytic”. Here “synthetic” means roughly “requires evidence” whereas “analytic” means roughly “obvious”.

Analytic presentation

An analytic presentation is only possible for certain kinds of object-theories, generally those which are type theories similar to LF itself. In this case, we represent object-theory types by LF-types themselves. Thus we still have the LF-type tptp of object-theory types, but instead of the LF-type tmtm of terms and the dependent LF-type ofof representing the object-theory typing judgment, we have

  • a dependent LF-type el:tpTypeel : tp \to Type

which assigns to each object-theory type, the LF-type of its elements. In other words, the typing judgment of the object-theory is encoded by the typing judgment of the meta-theory.

Now we have to make a choice about how to represent the definitional equality of the object-theory. A consistent choice is to also represent it by the definitional equality of the meta-theory. That is, in addition to merely giving “axioms” such as tptp and elel, we must give equations representing the rules of the object-theory as equalities in the logical framework. For instance, we must have a beta-reduction rule such as

app A B (lam A B F) M = F M

If the object-theory is itself a dependent type theory whose only definitional equalities are beta-reductions like this, then if we make the coercion elel implicit, we can think of the resulting encoding as analogous to a pure type system with three sorts, tptp, TypeType, and KindKind, with tp:Typetp:Type and Type:KindType:Kind.

However, from a practical point-of-view, rather than extending the logical framework with ad hoc definitional equalities to represent a particular object-theory, often what is actually done is that equality is defined as another type family with explicitly-introduced constructors. In other words, we use the analytic representation of types, but the synthetic representation of definitional equality. For example, in Twelf, the above equation could be represented by first assuming an LF-type family

eq : {A:tp} el A -> el A -> type

(Twelf uses braces as notation for the dependent product), and then postulating a constant

beta : {A:tp} {B:tp} eq (app A B (lam A B F)) (F M)

in addition to the other axioms of equality.

The analytic encoding is associated with Martin-Lof. While convenient for the description of rules in type theories, it is often less appropriate for the purposes of metatheoretic analysis.

For instance, in the hybrid style with the LF-type family eqeq, the terms in el(A)el(A) will involve explicit coercions along equalities in eqeq. This destroys the adequacy theorem, since coercions along definitional equalities are generally silent in the usual presentation of a theory. Moreover, one must assert explicitly that dependent types respect definitional equalities, and for multiply-dependent types this requires dependent products in the object-theory.

On the other hand, the “fully analytic” version where definitional equalities in the object-theory are also definitional equalities in the meta-theory involves adding additional equations to the meta-theory, which in general can make it impossible to reason about. One needs a decision procedure for these equalities even to be able to check proofs.

Thus, analytic approaches are less general and flexible; they are best adapted to describing the rules and semantics of a dependent type theory, whereas synthetic approaches are better for reasoning about syntax and for studying more general object-theories.

Higher-order abstract syntax

In both synthetic and analytic presentations, we use higher-order abstract syntax (HOAS). Roughly, this means that variables in the object-theory are not terms of some LF-type, but are represented by actual LF-variables. For instance, when describing a type theory containing function types synthetically, we would have

  • an LF-term arr:tptptparr : tp \to tp \to tp, where for object-theory types A:tpA:tp and B:tpB:tp, the term arr(A,B):tparr(A,B):tp represents their function-type
  • an LF-term app:tmtmtmapp : tm \to tm \to tm, where app(f,a)app(f,a) represents the function application f(a)f(a)
  • an LF-term lam:(tmtm)tmlam : (tm \to tm) \to tm, representing lambda abstraction.

The point is that the argument of lamlam (the “body” of the lambda abstraction) is not a “term containing a free variable xx” but rather an LF-function from object-theory terms to object-theory terms. This is intended to be the function “substitute” which knows about the body of the lambda-abstraction, and when given an argument it substitutes it for the variable in that body and returns the result.

This approach completely avoids dealing with the problems of variable binding and substitution in the object language, by making use of the binding and substitution in the metalanguage LF. One might say that the variables in LF are the “universal notion of variable” which is merely reused by all object-theories.

The power of weak frameworks

It may be tempting to think of the LF-types such as tptp and tmtm as inductively defined by their specified constructors (such as arrarr for tptp, and appapp and lamlam for tmtm). However, this is incorrect; LF does not have inductive types. In fact, this weakness is essential in order to guarantee “adequacy” of the HOAS encoding.

Suppose, for instance, that tmtm were inductively defined inside of LF. Then we could define a function tmtmtm\to tm by pattern-matching on the structure of tmtm, doing one thing if tmtm were a lambda-abstraction and another thing if it were a function application. But such a function is definitely not the sort of thing that we want to be able to pass to the LF-function lamlam! By disallowing such matching, though, we can guarantee that the only functions tmtmtm\to tm we can define and pass to lamlam correspond to “substituting in a fixed term” as we intended.

As an even simpler example, suppose we consider an object-theory containing just one LF-type natnat together with constructors z:natz : nat and s:natnats : nat \to nat. Although we would like to think of natnat as representing the natural numbers, because of the lack of an induction principle, the LF-type natnatnat \to nat certainly cannot be shown to contain all the functions from natural numbers to natural numbers (essentially, we can only construct the constant functions and those incrementing their argument by a fixed constant). On the other hand, to some extent it is possible to get around this restriction by taking a relational rather than a functional point-of-view. For example, addition of natural numbers can be defined as a type family

add : nat -> nat -> nat -> type

together with a pair of constructors

add/z : {N:nat} add z N N.
add/s : {M:nat}{N:nat}{P:nat} add M N P -> add (s M) N (s P).

Now, it is still not possible to prove inside LF that addadd is a total functional relation (i.e., that for all M:nat and N:nat there exists a unique P:nat such that add M N P). However, in this case that is certainly easy to verify by inspection, and the Twelf proof assistant has facilities for verifying such properties automatically (though in general checking totality is better supported than checking uniqueness).

There are tricks one can play in order to use a HOAS-like representation even in a framework that has true inductive types such as Coq. For instance, XORN18 uses “parametrized HOAS” in which the higher-order functions take as domain an arbitrary, unspecified, type, thereby eliminating the possibility of defining functions inductively over elements of any specific type. However, this apparently requires parametricity axioms in order to work, which are consistent, but false in natural set-theoretic and categorical models.

Implementations

One of the uses of a logical framework is that as a type theory itself, it can be implemented in a computer. This provides a convenient system in which one can “program” the rules of any other specific type theory or logic which one wants to study.

For a list of logical framework implementations, see Specific logical Frameworks and Implementations.

Historically, the first logical framework implementation was Automath. The goal of the Automath project was to provide a tool for the formalization of mathematics without foundational prejudice. Many modern logical frameworks carry influences of this.

Then inspired by the development of Martin-Löf dependent type theory was the Edinburgh Logical Framework (ELF). The logic and type theory-approaches were later combined in the Elf language. This gave rise to Twelf.

Isabelle is a logical framework that does not have dependent types, but instead works in a “predicate logic” framework with only one layer of dependency, proof-irrelevant propositions over a base simply typed lambda calculus. Unlike Twelf, it is designed for practical use in working in object-languages rather than proving meta-theorems about them. Its most common application is to higher-order logic, but there are also Isabelle formulations of first-order logic, ZFC, and a general library for sequent calculus.

References

The original logical framework using a synthetic approach was introduced in

while the analytic version was proposed by

  • Per Martin-Lof, On the meanings of the logical constants and the justifications of the logical laws

General overview:

A number of examples of encoding object-theories into LF can be found in

  • Arnon Avron, Furio Honsell, Ian A. Mason, and Robert Pollack, Using typed lambda calculus to implement formal systems on a machine

Other references:

  • Bruno Xavier, Carlos Olarte, Giselle Reis, Vivek Nigam, Mechanizing Linear Logic in Coq, pdf
  • Mary Southern, Gopalan Nadathur, Towards a Logic for Reasoning About LF Specifications, arxiv

Last revised on January 3, 2023 at 20:08:12. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.