nLab factorization lemma

Contents

Context

Model category theory

model category, model \infty -category

Definitions

Morphisms

Universal constructions

Refinements

Producing new model structures

Presentation of (,1)(\infty,1)-categories

Model structures

for \infty-groupoids

for ∞-groupoids

for equivariant \infty-groupoids

for rational \infty-groupoids

for rational equivariant \infty-groupoids

for nn-groupoids

for \infty-groups

for \infty-algebras

general \infty-algebras

specific \infty-algebras

for stable/spectrum objects

for (,1)(\infty,1)-categories

for stable (,1)(\infty,1)-categories

for (,1)(\infty,1)-operads

for (n,r)(n,r)-categories

for (,1)(\infty,1)-sheaves / \infty-stacks

Homotopy theory

homotopy theory, (∞,1)-category theory, homotopy type theory

flavors: stable, equivariant, rational, p-adic, proper, geometric, cohesive, directed

models: topological, simplicial, localic, …

see also algebraic topology

Introductions

Definitions

Paths and cylinders

Homotopy groups

Basic facts

Theorems

Contents

Idea

The factorization lemma (Brown 73, prop. below) is a fundamental tool in the theory of categories of fibrant objects (dually: of cofibrant objects). It mimics one half of the factorization axioms in a model category in that it asserts that every morphism may be factored as, in particular, a weak equivalence followed by a fibration.

A key corollary of the factorization lemma is the statement, widely known as Ken Brown’s lemma (prop. below) which says that for a functor from a category of fibrant objects to be a homotopical functor, it is sufficient already that it sends acyclic fibrations to weak equivalences.

For more background, see also at Introduction to classical homotopy theory this lemma.

Factorization lemma

Let 𝒞\mathcal{C} be a category of fibrant objects.

Proposition

Let

Xp XX×Yp YY X \overset{p_{X}}{\leftarrow} X \times Y \overset{p_{Y}}{\rightarrow} Y

be a product in 𝒞\mathcal{C}. Then p Xp_{X} and p Yp_{Y} are fibrations.

Proof

By one of the axioms for a category of fibrant objects, 𝒞\mathcal{C} has a final object 11. We have the following.

1) The following diagram in 𝒞\mathcal{C} is a cartesian square.

X×Y p Y Y p X X 1 \array{ X \times Y & \overset{p_{Y}}{\to} & Y \\ p_{X} \downarrow & & \downarrow \\ X & \to & 1 \\ }

2) By one of the axioms for a category of fibrant objects, the arrows Y1Y \to 1 and X1X \to 1 are fibrations.

By one of the axioms for a category of fibrant objects, it follows from 1) and 2) that p Xp_{X} and p Yp_{Y} are fibrations.

Proposition

Let XX be an object of 𝒞\mathcal{C}. Let

Xp 0X×Xp 1X X \overset{p_{0}}{\leftarrow} X \times X \overset{p_{1}}{\rightarrow} X

be a product in 𝒞\mathcal{C}. By one of the axioms for a category of fibrant objects, there is a commutative diagram

X c X I Δ e X×X \array{ X & \overset{c}{\to} & X^I \\ & \underset{\Delta}{\searrow} & \downarrow e \\ & & X \times X }

in 𝒞\mathcal{C} in which cc is a weak equivalence, and in which ee is a fibration.

The arrow e 0:X IXe_0 : X^I \to X given by p 0ep_0 \circ e is a trivial fibration. The arrow e 1:X IXe_1 : X^I \to X given by p 1ep_1 \circ e is a trivial fibration.

Proof

We have the following.

1) The following diagram in 𝒞\mathcal{C} commutes.

X c X I id X e 0 X \array{ X & \overset{c}{\to} & X^I \\ & \underset{id_X}{\searrow} & \downarrow e_{0} \\ & & X }

2 By one of the axioms for a category of fibrant objects, id Xid_X is a weak equivalence.

By one of the axioms for a category of fibrant objects, we deduce from 1), 2), and the fact that cc is a weak equivalence, that e 0e_{0} is a weak equivalence.

An entirely analogous argument demonstrates that e 1e_{1} is a weak equivalence.

Proposition

(Factorization lemma)

Let f:XYf : X \to Y be an arrow of 𝒞\mathcal{C}. There is a commutative diagram

X j Z f g Y \array{ X & \overset{j}{\to} & Z \\ & \underset{f}{\searrow} & \downarrow g \\ & & Y }

in 𝒞\mathcal{C} such that the following hold.

1) The arrow g:ZYg : Z \to Y is a fibration.

2) There is a trivial fibration r:ZXr : Z \to X such that the following diagram in 𝒞\mathcal{C} commutes.

X j Z id r X \array{ X & \overset{j}{\to} & Z \\ & \underset{id}{\searrow} & \downarrow r \\ & & X }
Proof

We can construct the following diagram:

The triangle on the right exists with cc a weak equivalence and ee a fibration, as categories of fibrant objects have path objects. As ee is a fibration, we can pullback along f×idf \times id to get the upper-left pullback square. By the universal property of this pullback square, we can produce a unique XjZX \overset j \to Z which makes the top half of the diagram commute.

We let gg be the composite Zπ 1 ZX×Yπ 1 X×YYZ \overset{\pi_1^Z} \to X \times Y \overset{\pi_1^{X \times Y}} \to Y so that gj=fg \circ j = f; these are fibrations due to being a pullback of the fibration ee and a product projection (Fact 1), so their composite gg is a fibration too.

We let rr be the composite Zπ 1 ZX×Yπ 0 X×YXZ \overset{\pi_1^Z} \to X \times Y \overset{\pi_0^{X \times Y}} \to X so that rj=id Xr \circ j = id_X. As the upper square and lower square are both pullback squares, rr is the pullback of the morphism Y IeYπ 0 Y×YYY^I \overset{e} \to Y \overset{\pi_0^{Y\times Y}} \to Y (which is an acyclic fibration by Fact 2), hence rr is also an acyclic fibraiton.

Remark

That rr is a fibration can be demonstrated in exactly the same way as that gg is a fibration. It is to prove the stronger assertion that rr is a trivial fibration that the argument with which we concluded the proof is needed.

Remark

By the commutativity of the diagram

X j Z id r X \array{ X & \overset{j}{\to} & Z \\ & \underset{id}{\searrow} & \downarrow r \\ & & X }

and the fact that rr is a weak equivalence, we have, by one of the axioms for a category of fibrant objects, that jj is a weak equivalence.

Ken Brown’s lemma

Proposition

(Ken Brown’s lemma)

Let 𝒞\mathcal{C} be a category of fibrant objects. Let 𝒟\mathcal{D} be a category with weak equivalences. Let F:CDF : C \to D be a functor with the property that, for every arrow ff of 𝒞\mathcal{C} which is a trivial fibration, we have that F(f)F(f) is a weak equivalence.

Let w:XYw : X \to Y be an arrow of 𝒞\mathcal{C} which is a weak equivalence. Then F(w)F(w) is a weak equivalence.

Proof

By Proposition 3, there is a commutative diagram

X j Z w g Y \array{ X & \overset{j}{\to} & Z \\ & \underset{w}{\searrow} & \downarrow g \\ & & Y }

in 𝒞\mathcal{C} such that the following hold.

1) The arrow g:ZYg : Z \to Y is a fibration.

2) There is a trivial fibration r:ZXr : Z \to X such that the following diagram in 𝒞\mathcal{C} commutes.

X j Z id r X \array{ X & \overset{j}{\to} & Z \\ & \underset{id}{\searrow} & \downarrow r \\ & & X }

By the commutativity of the diagram

X j Z w g Y \array{ X & \overset{j}{\to} & Z \\ & \underset{w}{\searrow} & \downarrow g \\ & & Y }

and the fact that both jj and ww are weak equivalences, we have that gg is a weak equivalence, by one of the axioms for a category of fibrant objects.

By assumption, we thus have that F(g):F(Z)F(Y)F(g) : F(Z) \to F(Y) is a weak equivalence.

The following hold.

1) By the commutativity of the diagram

X j Z id r X \array{ X & \overset{j}{\to} & Z \\ & \underset{id}{\searrow} & \downarrow r \\ & & X }

in 𝒞\mathcal{C}, we have that the following diagram in 𝒟\mathcal{D} commutes.

F(X) F(j) F(Z) id F(r) F(X) \array{ F(X) & \overset{F(j)}{\to} & F(Z) \\ & \underset{id}{\searrow} & \downarrow F(r) \\ & & F(X) }

2) Since rr is a trivial fibration, we have by assumption that F(r)F(r) is a trivial fibration. In particular, F(r)F(r) is a weak equivalence.

3) By one of the axioms for a category with weak equivalences, we have that id:F(X)F(X)id : F(X) \to F(X) is a weak equivalence.

By 1), 2), 3) and one of the axioms for a category with weak equivalences, we have that F(j)F(j) is a weak equivalence.

The following diagram in 𝒞\mathcal{C} commutes.

F(X) F(j) F(Z) F(w) F(g) F(Y) \array{ F(X) & \overset{F(j)}{\to} & F(Z) \\ & \underset{F(w)}{\searrow} & \downarrow F(g) \\ & & F(Y) }

Since F(j)F(j) and F(g)F(g) are weak equivalences, we conclude, by one of the axioms for a category with weak equivalences, that F(w)F(w) is a weak equivalence.

Remark

In other words, FF is a homotopical functor.

Remark

If CC is the full subcategory of fibrant objects in a model category, then this corollary asserts that a right Quillen functor GG, which by its axioms is required only to preserve fibrations and trivial fibrations, preserves also weak equivalences between fibrant objects.

Remark

By the dual nature of model categories, we then get that a left Quillen functor preserves weak equivalences between cofibrant objects.

Computing a homotopy pullback by means of an ordinary pullback

Corollary

Let ACBA \to C \leftarrow B be a diagram between fibrant objects in a model category. Then the ordinary pullback A× C hBA \times_C^h B

A× C hB C I A×B C×C \array{ A \times_C^h B &\to& C^I \\ \downarrow && \downarrow \\ A \times B &\to& C \times C }

presents the homotopy pullback of the original diagram.

See the section Concrete constructions at homotopy pullback for more details on this.

Examples

  • For GG an ∞-group object in CC with delooping BG\mathbf{B}G, applying the factorization lemma to the point inclusion *BG* \to \mathbf{B}G yields a morphism *EGpBG* \stackrel{\simeq}{\to} \mathbf{E}G \stackrel{p}{\to} \mathbf{B}G. This exhibits a universal principal ∞-bundle for GG.

References

The factorization lemma is due to

The corollary commonly known as “Ken Brown’s lemma” does not appear explicitly in Brown 73; it does appear under this name in

Lecture notes:

A version in the setup of \infty-cosmoi is Lemma 2.1.6 in

Last revised on July 8, 2022 at 09:17:15. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.